The criticism of platos contribution to the political theory in the republic

Problem of Forms Concept of Forms is not the only or obvious logical conclusion.

The criticism of platos contribution to the political theory in the republic

The Question and the Strategy 1. After Socrates asks his host what it is like being old d—e and rich d —rather rude, we might think—Cephalus says that the best thing about wealth is that it can save us from being unjust and thus smooth the way for an agreeable afterlife d—b.

This is enough to prompt more questions, for Socrates wants to know what justice is. Predictably, Cephalus and then Polemarchus fail to define justice in a way that survives Socratic examination, but they continue to assume that justice is a valuable part of a good human life.

Thrasymachus erupts when he has had his fill of this conversation a—band he challenges the assumption that it is good to be just.

Introduction: The Question and the Strategy

The strong themselves, on this view, are better off disregarding justice and serving their own interests directly. See the entry on Callicles and Thrasymachus. The brothers pick up where Thrasymachus left off, providing reasons why most people think that justice is not intrinsically valuable but worth respecting only if one is not strong enough or invisible enough to get away with injustice.

The criticism of platos contribution to the political theory in the republic

They want to be shown that most people are wrong, that justice is worth choosing for its own sake. More than that, Glaucon and Adeimantus want to be shown that justice is worth choosing regardless of the rewards or penalties bestowed on the just by other people and the gods, and they will accept this conclusion only if Socrates can convince them that it is always better to be just.

So Socrates must persuade them that the just person who is terrifically unfortunate and scorned lives a better life than the unjust person who is so successful that he is unfairly rewarded as if he were perfectly just see d—d.

The challenge that Glaucon and Adeimantus present has baffled modern readers who are accustomed to carving up ethics into deontologies that articulate a theory of what is right independent of what is good and consequentialisms that define what is right in terms of what promotes the good FosterMabbottcf.

The criticism of platos contribution to the political theory in the republic

Prichard and But the insistence that justice be shown to be beneficial to the just has suggested to others that Socrates will be justifying justice by reference to its consequences. In fact, both readings are distortions, predicated more on what modern moral philosophers think than on what Plato thinks.

At the beginning of Book Two, he retains his focus on the person who aims to be happy. But he does not have to show that being just or acting justly brings about happiness. The function argument in Book One suggests that acting justly is the same as being happy.

But the function argument concludes that justice is both necessary and sufficient for happiness aand this is a considerably stronger thesis than the claim that the just are always happier than the unjust.

Keep Exploring Britannica

After the challenge Glaucon and Adeimantus present, Socrates might not be so bold. Even if he successfully maintains that acting justly is identical to being happy, he might think that there are circumstances in which no just person could act justly and thus be happy.

This will nonetheless satisfy Glaucon and Adeimantus if the just are better off that is, closer to happy than the unjust in these circumstances.

See also Kirwan and Irwin Some think that Plato does not intend the Republic as a serious contribution to political thought, because its political musings are projections to clarify psychological claims crucial to the ethical theory that Plato does seriously intend (Annas , Annas ).

Others think that Plato intends political lessons strikingly different from what is suggested by the face value of Socrates’ words. Although the Republic, the Statesman, the Laws and a few shorter dialogues are considered to be the only strictly political dialogues of Plato, it can be argued that political philosophy was the area of his greatest concern.

In the English-speaking world, under the influence of twentieth century analytic philosophy, the main task of political philosophy today is still often seen as conceptual analysis: the . Plato’s withering criticisms of Athenian democracy in the Gorgias (ca.

Plato: Political Philosophy | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

BCE) and to a lesser extent in other works, such as the Apology of Socrates (ca. BCE), culminate in detailed exploration of a completely just city in the Republic (ca.

BCE), Plato’s best-known political work. Platon a deux frères, Adimante et Glaucon, sans doute plus jeunes que lui [11], ainsi qu'une sœur, Pôtonê (mère de Speusippe, successeur de Platon à la tête de l’Académie [8]).La mère de Platon, veuve quelque temps après sa naissance, se remarie avec son oncle maternel, Pyrilampe.

Plato's Republic Critics of The Republic, Plato's contribution to the history of political theory, have formed two distinct opinions on the reasoning behind the work.

The chapter concludes by considering Plato’s own rhetorical practice in politics and philosophy, both in the political arrangements of the Republic and Laws and in the manner in which his early and middle dialogues seek to persuade nonphilosophical readers to adopt philosophical values.

Aristotle's Political Theory (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)